Top-down definition Psychology

  • NCBI
    Top-down definition Psychology
  • Skip to main content
  • Skip to navigation
  • Resources
  • How To
  • About NCBI Accesskeys
My NCBISign in to NCBISign Out

PMC

US National Library of Medicine
National Institutes of Health
Search database
Search term
Search
  • Advanced
  • Journal list
  • Help

Try out PMC Labs and tell us what you think. Learn More.

  • Journal List
  • J Cogn
  • v.1(1); 2018
  • PMC6147259
Top-down definition Psychology
J Cogn. 2018; 1(1): 25.
Published online 2018 May 14. doi:10.5334/joc.28
PMCID: PMC6147259
NIHMSID: NIHMS986038
PMID: 30246170

Top-down Does Not Mean Voluntary

Nicholas Gaspelin1 and Steven J. Luck2

Nicholas Gaspelin

1Binghamton University, State University of New York, US

Find articles by Nicholas Gaspelin

Steven J. Luck

2University of California, Davis, US

Find articles by Steven J. Luck
Author information Article notes Copyright and License information Disclaimer
1Binghamton University, State University of New York, US
2University of California, Davis, US
Nicholas Gaspelin: ude.notmahgnib@nilepsag
Corresponding author: Nicholas Gaspelin (ude.notmahgnib@nilepsag)
Received 2018 Feb 21; Accepted 2018 Mar 15.
Copyright : © 2018 The Author(s)
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC-BY 4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
This article has been cited by other articles in PMC.

Abstract

Attention researchers have long debated the roles of top-down and bottom-up mechanisms in controlling attention. Theeuwes (2018) has argued that that top-down control is much less common than typically assumed and that a third mechanismselection historyplays an underappreciated role in guiding visual attention. Although Theeuwes has made a strong case for the importance of selection history, his arguments for a limited role of top-down mechanisms involve conflating the terms top-down and voluntary. Cognitive psychologists typically use the term top-down processing to refer to any perceptual phenomenon that is influenced by context, learning, or expectation, which would include selection history. This highlights a broad problem in attention capture research: The terms used to describe attentional control are often poorly defined, and much current debate seems to be related to the meaning of words. To move forward in understanding the actual mechanisms of attentional control, we must agree on what terms such as top-down and bottom-up actually mean.

Keywords: attentional capture, visual attention, selection history

Traditionally, mechanisms of attentional control have been divided into two distinct classes: top-down and bottom-up. Theeuwes (2018) argues for the inclusion of a third mechanism that may guide attentional allocation: selection history. According to this account, implicit mechanisms such as priming or reward history may explain a large amount of the guidance of visual attention. We agree with many of the key points of this review, especially the likelihood that much of attentional guidance is involuntary and unconscious. However, we disagree with the way that Theeuwes has conflated the terms top-down and voluntary. In this commentary, we will demonstrate that these terms have traditionally meant very different things in the literature on perception and cognition, and we will argue that conflating them leads to confusion rather than clarity.

Why Terminology Matters

It might seem petty for us to focus on the definition of one little word. After all, shouldnt we be focusing on the data? However, standardized terminology is crucial for scientific progress. Consider a hypothetical debate about whether the sky is blue. One group of researchers defines blue as one color (which would look light blue to most of us). They conclude the sky is blue. However, another group of researchers defines blue as a different color (which would look dark blue to most of us). They conclude the sky is not blue. These two theoretical camps will be doomed to debate forever or at least until they can agree upon a common definition of the word blue. Perhaps the most depressing part of this parable is that both camps agree on the actual spectral content of the sky but believe they disagree because they are using different terms for the same color. Most of us would agree that this hypothetical debate is silly. But it illustrates a key problem. If we cannot agree upon the meanings of top-down and bottom-up, there is little hope for reaching consensus about the mechanisms of attentional control.

Top-down versus voluntary

Theeuwes (2018) defines top-down as being equivalent to voluntary or intentional. He states that top-down attention is relatively slow (p. 18), that top-down selection is controlled (p. 18) rather than automatic, and that top-down selection requires effort to shift attention (p. 19). He also provides several quotes from attention researchers showing that they often stress the voluntary aspects of top-down attentional control. However, close inspection of these quotes reveals that several of the researchers considered voluntary attentional control to be a subset of top-down attentional control and not equivalent to top-down. For example, the statement that voluntary orienting can be considered aspects of top-down attentional control (Hopfinger, Buonocore, & Mangun, 2000, p. 284), implies that there are also involuntary forms of top-down control (because otherwise the modifier would be unnecessary). Similarly, Baluch and Itti (2011) are cited because they used the phrase volitional top-down process. But the glossary of that paper clearly distinguishes between volitional top-down processes and top-down processes more generally. A top-down process is defined by Baluch and Itti as an automatic, percept-modifying [top-down] mechanism that is pervasive and that volition cannot completely eliminate. (p. 210). Similarly, a classic study of contextual cuing (Chun & Jiang, 1999) is titled, Top-down attentional guidance based on implicit learning of visual covariation, which makes a clear distinction between top-down control and explicit, voluntary control. Thus, top-down is not equivalent to voluntary in common usage.

So, what does top-down mean? Traditionally, top-down perception refers to situations in which context, learning, or expectation alters a perceptual process. For example, a standard introductory psychology textbook provides the following definition: Top-down processing is how knowledge, expectations, or past experiences shape the interpretation of sensory information (Gazzaniga, Heatherton, & Halpern, 2016, p. 173). Another introductory psychology textbook defines top-down as: Cognitive (usually perceptual) process directed by expectations (derived from context, past, learning, or both) to form a larger percept, concept, or interpretation (Galotti, 2014, p. 423). This is echoed in the scientific literature by Baluch and Itti (2011), who define top-down influence as influence on the nervous system due to extra-retinal effects such as intrinsic expectations, knowledge and goals. All of these definitions say nothing about awareness or intentionality, but do include past experiences (such as selection history).

A common textbook illustration of top-down perception is shown in Figure Figure1.1. The A in CAT and the H in THE are exactly the same shape, but top-down knowledge of common English words allows experienced readers to read the words as CAT and THE without even realizing that they could be seen as CHT and TAE. Few would assert that this classic example of top-down processing is voluntary (slow, controlled, and effortful). Another common example of top-down perception is the auditory phonemic restoration effect, in which a masked sound within a speech signal is restored for familiar but not unfamiliar words (Samuel, 1981). No one would argue that phonemic restoration is voluntary.

Top-down definition Psychology
Open in a separate window
Figure 1

Illustration of a top-down perceptual phenomenon that does not seem voluntary or intentional (adapted from Selfridge, 1955). The a in cat and the h in the the have the same letter shape. However, people effortlessly see the words CAT and THE rather than CHT and TAE.

Using top-down to mean voluntary is just not the correct way to use these terms. But, we can understand why the term top-down can be confusing. Attention capture researchers often use imprecise language, and we ourselves have been certainly guilty of this. For example, we frequently used the phrase goal-driven theory when referring to theories in which intentions or expectations can indirectly lead to the capture of attention by stimuli that shared features with the target (Gaspelin, Leonard, & Luck, 2015, 2017, Gaspelin & Luck, in press, 2018). We did not mean to imply that the observers had the goal of focusing attention on these stimuli. Instead, we assumed that the explicit task goal triggered a cascade of events that led ultimately to the capture stimuli that matched the features of the target but were entirely task irrelevant (see Folk, Remington, & Johnston, 1992, for a particularly clear formulation). However, we never made this logic explicit, and it is easy to understand that the term goal-driven could be taken to imply direct, voluntary control of attention. And herein lies the problem common terminology in this area can easily be misinterpreted.

It is worth mentioning that many researchers advocating for selection history have avoided conflating top-down processing with volition. Most notably, a recent review by Awh, Belopolsky, and Theeuwes (2012) defined top-down control as attentional control that is driven by factors that are internal to the observer (p. 437). This effectively defines top-down as everything that is not bottom-up, forming a clean dichotomy that is consistent with historical usage of the term top-down. That article made a compelling argument that the top-down/bottom-up dichotomy has been problematic as a research strategy, because some forms of top-down control are voluntary, slow, and controlled, whereas others are largely involuntary, fast, and automatic. However, this implies that the field should undergo a shift in research strategy, not change the definition of top-down.

Conclusion

We agree with Theeuwes (2018) that selection history is an important avenue for future research and that it shares many key properties with bottom-up control. However, selection history is clearly a form of top-down attentional control as this term has historically been used, and redefining top-down to mean voluntary would be inconsistent with the rest of the field and inevitably lead to confusion rather than progress. On the other hand, top-down theories of attention capture have often focused on forms of top-down guidance that are very different from selection history. For example, the contingent involuntary orienting hypothesis (Folk et al., 1992) proposes that participants form a voluntary attentional set that sometimes leads to capture of attention by irrelevant items, and this is very different from something like automatic priming from previous trials. Similarly, the concepts of singleton detection mode and feature search mode (Bacon & Egeth, 1994) seem very much like voluntary strategies rather than unconsciously learned effects of selection history. As Theeuwes (2018) points out, disentangling conscious top-down strategies from selection history will require moving away from paradigms in which participants perform the same task for a long block of trials and instead using trial-by-trial cuing paradigms. Such paradigms, when used with well-defined terminology, will allow the field to move forward in understanding the roles of volition, awareness, automaticity, selection history, bottom-up processes, and top-down processes in the guidance of attention.

Competing Interests

The authors have no competing interests to declare.

Author Information

This study was made possible by NIH Grants R01MH076226 and R01MH065034 to S.J.L.

References

1. Awh, E., Belopolsky, A. V., & Theeuwes, J. (2012). Top-down versus bottom-up attentional control: A failed theoretical dichotomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(8), 437443. DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2012.06.010 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
2. Bacon, W. F., & Egeth, H. E. (1994). Overriding stimulus-driven attentional capture. Perception & Psychophysics, 55(5), 485496. DOI: 10.3758/BF03205306 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
3. Baluch, F., & Itti, L. (2011). Mechanisms of top-down attention. Trends in Neurosciences, 34(4), 210224. DOI: 10.1016/j.tins.2011.02.003 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
4. Chun, M. M., & Jiang, Y. (1999). Top-down attentiaonal guidance based on implicit learning of visual covariation. Psychological Science, 10(4), 360365. DOI: 10.1111/1467-9280.00168 [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
5. Folk, C. L., Remington, R. W., & Johnston, J. C. (1992). Involuntary covert orienting is contingent on attentional control settings. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18(4), 10301044. DOI: 10.1037/0096-1523.18.4.1030 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
6. Galotti, K. M. (2014). Cognitive Psychology: In and Out of the Laboratory (Fifth). Los Angeles: SAGE. [Google Scholar]
7. Gaspelin, N., Leonard, C. J., & Luck, S. J. (2015). Direct evidence for active suppression of salient-but-irrelevant sensory Iiputs. Psychological Science, 22(11), 17401750. DOI: 10.1177/0956797615597913 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
8. Gaspelin, N., Leonard, C. J., & Luck, S. J. (2017). Suppression of overt attentional capture by salient-but-irrelevant color singletons. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 79(1), 118. DOI: 10.3758/s13414-016-1209-1 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
9. Gaspelin, N., & Luck, S. J. (2018). The role of inhibition in avoiding distraction by salient stimuli. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22(1), 7992. DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2017.11.001 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
10. Gaspelin, N., & Luck, S. J. (in press). Distinguishing among potential mechanisms of singleton suppression. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance. DOI: 10.1037/xhp0000484 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
11. Gazzaniga, M. S., Heatherton, T. F., & Halpern, D. (2016). Psychological Science (5th Edition). New York: W. W. Norton and Company. [Google Scholar]
12. Hopfinger, J. B., Buonocore, M. H., & Mangun, G. R. (2000). The neural mechanisms of top-down attentional control. Nature Neuroscience, 3(3), 284291. DOI: 10.1038/72999 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
13. Samuel, A. G. (1981). Phonemic restoration: insights from a new methodology. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 110(474). DOI: 10.1037/0096-3445.110.4.474 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
14. Selfridge, O. G. (1955). Pattern recogntion and modern computers. Proceedings of the Western Joirn Computer Conference. [Google Scholar]
15. Theeuwes, J. (2018). Visual Selection: Usually Fast and Automatic; Seldom Slow and Volitional. 1(1), 29. DOI: 10.5334/joc.13 [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Journal of Cognition are provided here courtesy of Ubiquity Press

Formats:

  • Article
  • |
  • PubReader
  • |
  • ePub (beta)
  • |
  • PDF (354K)
  • |
  • Cite
Support Center Support Center
External link. Please review our privacy policy.
NLM
NIH
DHHS
USA.gov

National Center for Biotechnology Information, U.S. National Library of Medicine 8600 Rockville Pike, Bethesda MD, 20894 USA

Policies and Guidelines | Contact
J Cogn. 2018; 1(1): 25.
Published online 2018 May 14. doi:10.5334/joc.28
PMCID: PMC6147259
NIHMSID: NIHMS986038
PMID: 30246170

Top-down Does Not Mean Voluntary

Nicholas Gaspelin1 and Steven J. Luck2

Nicholas Gaspelin

1Binghamton University, State University of New York, US

Find articles by Nicholas Gaspelin

Steven J. Luck

2University of California, Davis, US

Find articles by Steven J. Luck
Author information Article notes Copyright and License information Disclaimer
1Binghamton University, State University of New York, US
2University of California, Davis, US
Nicholas Gaspelin: ude.notmahgnib@nilepsag
Corresponding author: Nicholas Gaspelin (ude.notmahgnib@nilepsag)
Received 2018 Feb 21; Accepted 2018 Mar 15.
Copyright : © 2018 The Author(s)
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC-BY 4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
This article has been cited by other articles in PMC.

Abstract

Attention researchers have long debated the roles of top-down and bottom-up mechanisms in controlling attention. Theeuwes (2018) has argued that that top-down control is much less common than typically assumed and that a third mechanismselection historyplays an underappreciated role in guiding visual attention. Although Theeuwes has made a strong case for the importance of selection history, his arguments for a limited role of top-down mechanisms involve conflating the terms top-down and voluntary. Cognitive psychologists typically use the term top-down processing to refer to any perceptual phenomenon that is influenced by context, learning, or expectation, which would include selection history. This highlights a broad problem in attention capture research: The terms used to describe attentional control are often poorly defined, and much current debate seems to be related to the meaning of words. To move forward in understanding the actual mechanisms of attentional control, we must agree on what terms such as top-down and bottom-up actually mean.

Keywords: attentional capture, visual attention, selection history

Traditionally, mechanisms of attentional control have been divided into two distinct classes: top-down and bottom-up. Theeuwes (2018) argues for the inclusion of a third mechanism that may guide attentional allocation: selection history. According to this account, implicit mechanisms such as priming or reward history may explain a large amount of the guidance of visual attention. We agree with many of the key points of this review, especially the likelihood that much of attentional guidance is involuntary and unconscious. However, we disagree with the way that Theeuwes has conflated the terms top-down and voluntary. In this commentary, we will demonstrate that these terms have traditionally meant very different things in the literature on perception and cognition, and we will argue that conflating them leads to confusion rather than clarity.

Why Terminology Matters

It might seem petty for us to focus on the definition of one little word. After all, shouldnt we be focusing on the data? However, standardized terminology is crucial for scientific progress. Consider a hypothetical debate about whether the sky is blue. One group of researchers defines blue as one color (which would look light blue to most of us). They conclude the sky is blue. However, another group of researchers defines blue as a different color (which would look dark blue to most of us). They conclude the sky is not blue. These two theoretical camps will be doomed to debate forever or at least until they can agree upon a common definition of the word blue. Perhaps the most depressing part of this parable is that both camps agree on the actual spectral content of the sky but believe they disagree because they are using different terms for the same color. Most of us would agree that this hypothetical debate is silly. But it illustrates a key problem. If we cannot agree upon the meanings of top-down and bottom-up, there is little hope for reaching consensus about the mechanisms of attentional control.

Top-down versus voluntary

Theeuwes (2018) defines top-down as being equivalent to voluntary or intentional. He states that top-down attention is relatively slow (p. 18), that top-down selection is controlled (p. 18) rather than automatic, and that top-down selection requires effort to shift attention (p. 19). He also provides several quotes from attention researchers showing that they often stress the voluntary aspects of top-down attentional control. However, close inspection of these quotes reveals that several of the researchers considered voluntary attentional control to be a subset of top-down attentional control and not equivalent to top-down. For example, the statement that voluntary orienting can be considered aspects of top-down attentional control (Hopfinger, Buonocore, & Mangun, 2000, p. 284), implies that there are also involuntary forms of top-down control (because otherwise the modifier would be unnecessary). Similarly, Baluch and Itti (2011) are cited because they used the phrase volitional top-down process. But the glossary of that paper clearly distinguishes between volitional top-down processes and top-down processes more generally. A top-down process is defined by Baluch and Itti as an automatic, percept-modifying [top-down] mechanism that is pervasive and that volition cannot completely eliminate. (p. 210). Similarly, a classic study of contextual cuing (Chun & Jiang, 1999) is titled, Top-down attentional guidance based on implicit learning of visual covariation, which makes a clear distinction between top-down control and explicit, voluntary control. Thus, top-down is not equivalent to voluntary in common usage.

So, what does top-down mean? Traditionally, top-down perception refers to situations in which context, learning, or expectation alters a perceptual process. For example, a standard introductory psychology textbook provides the following definition: Top-down processing is how knowledge, expectations, or past experiences shape the interpretation of sensory information (Gazzaniga, Heatherton, & Halpern, 2016, p. 173). Another introductory psychology textbook defines top-down as: Cognitive (usually perceptual) process directed by expectations (derived from context, past, learning, or both) to form a larger percept, concept, or interpretation (Galotti, 2014, p. 423). This is echoed in the scientific literature by Baluch and Itti (2011), who define top-down influence as influence on the nervous system due to extra-retinal effects such as intrinsic expectations, knowledge and goals. All of these definitions say nothing about awareness or intentionality, but do include past experiences (such as selection history).

A common textbook illustration of top-down perception is shown in Figure Figure1.1. The A in CAT and the H in THE are exactly the same shape, but top-down knowledge of common English words allows experienced readers to read the words as CAT and THE without even realizing that they could be seen as CHT and TAE. Few would assert that this classic example of top-down processing is voluntary (slow, controlled, and effortful). Another common example of top-down perception is the auditory phonemic restoration effect, in which a masked sound within a speech signal is restored for familiar but not unfamiliar words (Samuel, 1981). No one would argue that phonemic restoration is voluntary.

Top-down definition Psychology
Open in a separate window
Figure 1

Illustration of a top-down perceptual phenomenon that does not seem voluntary or intentional (adapted from Selfridge, 1955). The a in cat and the h in the the have the same letter shape. However, people effortlessly see the words CAT and THE rather than CHT and TAE.

Using top-down to mean voluntary is just not the correct way to use these terms. But, we can understand why the term top-down can be confusing. Attention capture researchers often use imprecise language, and we ourselves have been certainly guilty of this. For example, we frequently used the phrase goal-driven theory when referring to theories in which intentions or expectations can indirectly lead to the capture of attention by stimuli that shared features with the target (Gaspelin, Leonard, & Luck, 2015, 2017, Gaspelin & Luck, in press, 2018). We did not mean to imply that the observers had the goal of focusing attention on these stimuli. Instead, we assumed that the explicit task goal triggered a cascade of events that led ultimately to the capture stimuli that matched the features of the target but were entirely task irrelevant (see Folk, Remington, & Johnston, 1992, for a particularly clear formulation). However, we never made this logic explicit, and it is easy to understand that the term goal-driven could be taken to imply direct, voluntary control of attention. And herein lies the problem common terminology in this area can easily be misinterpreted.

It is worth mentioning that many researchers advocating for selection history have avoided conflating top-down processing with volition. Most notably, a recent review by Awh, Belopolsky, and Theeuwes (2012) defined top-down control as attentional control that is driven by factors that are internal to the observer (p. 437). This effectively defines top-down as everything that is not bottom-up, forming a clean dichotomy that is consistent with historical usage of the term top-down. That article made a compelling argument that the top-down/bottom-up dichotomy has been problematic as a research strategy, because some forms of top-down control are voluntary, slow, and controlled, whereas others are largely involuntary, fast, and automatic. However, this implies that the field should undergo a shift in research strategy, not change the definition of top-down.

Conclusion

We agree with Theeuwes (2018) that selection history is an important avenue for future research and that it shares many key properties with bottom-up control. However, selection history is clearly a form of top-down attentional control as this term has historically been used, and redefining top-down to mean voluntary would be inconsistent with the rest of the field and inevitably lead to confusion rather than progress. On the other hand, top-down theories of attention capture have often focused on forms of top-down guidance that are very different from selection history. For example, the contingent involuntary orienting hypothesis (Folk et al., 1992) proposes that participants form a voluntary attentional set that sometimes leads to capture of attention by irrelevant items, and this is very different from something like automatic priming from previous trials. Similarly, the concepts of singleton detection mode and feature search mode (Bacon & Egeth, 1994) seem very much like voluntary strategies rather than unconsciously learned effects of selection history. As Theeuwes (2018) points out, disentangling conscious top-down strategies from selection history will require moving away from paradigms in which participants perform the same task for a long block of trials and instead using trial-by-trial cuing paradigms. Such paradigms, when used with well-defined terminology, will allow the field to move forward in understanding the roles of volition, awareness, automaticity, selection history, bottom-up processes, and top-down processes in the guidance of attention.

Competing Interests

The authors have no competing interests to declare.

Author Information

This study was made possible by NIH Grants R01MH076226 and R01MH065034 to S.J.L.

References

1. Awh, E., Belopolsky, A. V., & Theeuwes, J. (2012). Top-down versus bottom-up attentional control: A failed theoretical dichotomy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(8), 437443. DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2012.06.010 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
2. Bacon, W. F., & Egeth, H. E. (1994). Overriding stimulus-driven attentional capture. Perception & Psychophysics, 55(5), 485496. DOI: 10.3758/BF03205306 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
3. Baluch, F., & Itti, L. (2011). Mechanisms of top-down attention. Trends in Neurosciences, 34(4), 210224. DOI: 10.1016/j.tins.2011.02.003 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
4. Chun, M. M., & Jiang, Y. (1999). Top-down attentiaonal guidance based on implicit learning of visual covariation. Psychological Science, 10(4), 360365. DOI: 10.1111/1467-9280.00168 [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
5. Folk, C. L., Remington, R. W., & Johnston, J. C. (1992). Involuntary covert orienting is contingent on attentional control settings. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 18(4), 10301044. DOI: 10.1037/0096-1523.18.4.1030 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
6. Galotti, K. M. (2014). Cognitive Psychology: In and Out of the Laboratory (Fifth). Los Angeles: SAGE. [Google Scholar]
7. Gaspelin, N., Leonard, C. J., & Luck, S. J. (2015). Direct evidence for active suppression of salient-but-irrelevant sensory Iiputs. Psychological Science, 22(11), 17401750. DOI: 10.1177/0956797615597913 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
8. Gaspelin, N., Leonard, C. J., & Luck, S. J. (2017). Suppression of overt attentional capture by salient-but-irrelevant color singletons. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 79(1), 118. DOI: 10.3758/s13414-016-1209-1 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
9. Gaspelin, N., & Luck, S. J. (2018). The role of inhibition in avoiding distraction by salient stimuli. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 22(1), 7992. DOI: 10.1016/j.tics.2017.11.001 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
10. Gaspelin, N., & Luck, S. J. (in press). Distinguishing among potential mechanisms of singleton suppression. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance. DOI: 10.1037/xhp0000484 [PMC free article] [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
11. Gazzaniga, M. S., Heatherton, T. F., & Halpern, D. (2016). Psychological Science (5th Edition). New York: W. W. Norton and Company. [Google Scholar]
12. Hopfinger, J. B., Buonocore, M. H., & Mangun, G. R. (2000). The neural mechanisms of top-down attentional control. Nature Neuroscience, 3(3), 284291. DOI: 10.1038/72999 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
13. Samuel, A. G. (1981). Phonemic restoration: insights from a new methodology. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 110(474). DOI: 10.1037/0096-3445.110.4.474 [PubMed] [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]
14. Selfridge, O. G. (1955). Pattern recogntion and modern computers. Proceedings of the Western Joirn Computer Conference. [Google Scholar]
15. Theeuwes, J. (2018). Visual Selection: Usually Fast and Automatic; Seldom Slow and Volitional. 1(1), 29. DOI: 10.5334/joc.13 [CrossRef] [Google Scholar]

Articles from Journal of Cognition are provided here courtesy of Ubiquity Press